next up previous
Next: Cardinal functions in analysis Up: Set Theoretic Real Analysis Previous: New developments in classical

New classic-like results

Consider the functions tex2html_wrap_inline5597 from tex2html_wrap_inline5075 onto tex2html_wrap_inline5111. By a well known theorem of Peano from 1890 (see e.g. [117]) such an F can be continuous. However, it is not difficult to see that it cannot be differentiable. It follows easily from the fact that every differentiable function tex2html_wrap_inline5367 satisfies the Banach condition tex2html_wrap_inline5607, i.e., the set tex2html_wrap_inline5609 has Lebesgue measure zero. (See e.g. [118, Chap. VII, p. 221,].) Thus, Morayne in 1987 considered the following question: can function tex2html_wrap_inline5597 be chosen in such a way that at every point tex2html_wrap_inline5413 either tex2html_wrap_inline5615 or tex2html_wrap_inline5617 is differentiable? The surprising answer is given below.


 theorem2155

The proof of this theorem is based on a well known theorem of Sierpinski [127, Property tex2html_wrap_inline5631,] from 1919 that CH is equivalent to the existence of a decomposition of tex2html_wrap_inline5111 into two sets A and B such that all horizontal section of A and all vertical section of B are at most countable. It is also worthwhile to point out that the function F from Theorem 3.1 is not a Peano curve, since it is not continuous. In fact Morayne proves in the same paper that for such an tex2html_wrap_inline5597 it is impossible that even one of tex2html_wrap_inline5615 or tex2html_wrap_inline5617 is measurable.

Next, recall that if two continuous functions tex2html_wrap_inline5651 agree on some dense set tex2html_wrap_inline5653 then they are equal. Does the statement remain true if the clause ``agree on M'' is replaced by ``f[M]=g[M]?'' Clearly not, as shown by tex2html_wrap_inline5659 and any two different rational translations of the identity function. What about finding some more complicated set tex2html_wrap_inline5653 for which the implication
displaymath5587
holds for any continuous f and g? Even this is too much to ask, as recently noted by Burke and Ciesielski [18, Remark 6.6,]. On the other hand, the following theorem of Berarducci and Dikranjan from 1993 gives a positive (consistent) answer to this question in the class of continuous nowhere constant functions. (Function is nowhere constant if it is not constant on any non-empty open set.)


 theorem2160

The construction of a magic set, given in [8], is done by an easy diagonal transfinite induction argument, and uses only the assumption that less than continuum many meager sets do not cover tex2html_wrap_inline5075. In particular, CH can be replaced by MA in Theorem 3.2.

Examining the problem of existence of a magic set in ZFC Burke and Ciesielski noticed the following properties of a magic set.


 theorem2167

In fact part (b) of Theorem 3.3 is just a remark: if there were a continuous tex2html_wrap_inline5367 with tex2html_wrap_inline5691 then it could be easily modified to a nowhere constant function such that tex2html_wrap_inline5693, and the functions f and g=1+f would give a contradiction. But (b) shows that there is no magic set of cardinality continuum in the model from Theorem 2.4, the iterated perfect set model. Although it was noticed in [18] that in this model there exists a magic set (clearly of cardinality less than tex2html_wrap_inline5125), Theorem 3.3 was used by Ciesielski and Shelah as a base in proving that magic set cannot be constructed in ZFC.


 theorem2175

The magic sets for different classes of functions have also been considered. Burke and Ciesielski [18] studied such sets (which they call sets of range uniqueness) for the classes of measurable functions with respect to abstract measurable spaces with negligibles. In particular, they proved the following theorem concerning the Lebesgue measurable functions.


 theorem2183

The model satisfying Theorem 3.5(b) is a modification the iterated perfect set model and was constructed by Corazza [46] in 1989. Once again it satisfies property (b) of Theorem 3.4, while part (a) is replaced by tex2html_wrap_inline5233. It has been also proved by Ciesielski and Larson that for the class of tex2html_wrap_inline5723 functions (continuously differentiable) the existence of a magic set can be proved in ZFC.


 theorem2197

For the following consideration recall that a function tex2html_wrap_inline5735 is Darboux (or has the Darboux property) if f[C] is connected for every connected subset C of tex2html_wrap_inline5741. Thus, in case of n=1 Darboux functions are precisely the functions for which the Intermediate Value Theorem holds. The class of Darboux functions will be denoted here by tex2html_wrap_inline5745 (with n clear from the context, usually n=1).

The class of Darboux functions has been studied for a long time as one of possible generalizations of the class of continuous functions. (Clearly every continuous function is Darboux.) However, it has some peculiar properties. For example, it is not closed under addition. In fact, in 1927 Lindenbaum [92] noticed (without a proof) that every function tex2html_wrap_inline5367 can be written as a sum of two Darboux functions. (For proofs, see [129, ].) This theorem has been improved in several ways. Erdos [52] showed that if f is measurable, both of the summands can be chosen to be measurable. Another improvement was done by Fast [53] in 1974 who proved that for every family tex2html_wrap_inline5755 of real functions that has cardinality continuum there is just one Darboux function g such that the sum of g with any function in tex2html_wrap_inline5755 has the Darboux property. The natural question of whether such a ``universal'' summand exists also for families of larger cardinality has been studied by Natkaniec [104] and lead to the development described in Section 4.

A problem that is in some sense opposite to the existence of a ``universal'' summand is for which families tex2html_wrap_inline5755 of functions there is a ``universally bad'' Darboux function g, in the sense that the sum of g with any function in tex2html_wrap_inline5755 does not have the Darboux property. In 1990 Kirchheim and Natkaniec addressed this problem for the class tex2html_wrap_inline5755 of continuous nowhere constant functions.


 theorem2209

The problem whether the additional set-theoretic assumptions are necessary in this theorem was investigated in 1992 by Komjáth [81] and was settled in 1995 by Steprans.


 theorem2215

A model having this property is the iterated perfect set model. Note also that in Theorem 3.7 the restriction to the nowhere constant functions is important. This has been proved independently by T. Natkaniec (in his 1992/93 paper [106]) and by J. Steprans (in the 1995 paper mentioned above).


 theorem2220

To state farther results recall the following generalizations of continuity. A function tex2html_wrap_inline5735 is almost continuous (in sense of Stallings) if each open subset of tex2html_wrap_inline5797 containing the graph of f contains also a continuous function from tex2html_wrap_inline5741 to tex2html_wrap_inline5075 [132]. Function tex2html_wrap_inline5367 has a perfect road at tex2html_wrap_inline5413 if there exists a perfect set C such that x is a bilateral limit point of C and tex2html_wrap_inline5815 is continuous at x [97]. The classes of all almost continuous functions and all functions having a perfect road at each point are denoted by tex2html_wrap_inline5819 and tex2html_wrap_inline5821, respectively. It is easy to see that tex2html_wrap_inline5823 (for functions on tex2html_wrap_inline5075) and that the inclusions are strict (see e.g. [13]), where tex2html_wrap_inline5827 stands for the class of all continuous functions. We will also consider the class tex2html_wrap_inline5829 of Sierpinski-Zygmund (SZ-) functions, i.e., functions tex2html_wrap_inline5367 whose restrictions tex2html_wrap_inline5373 are discontinuous for all subsets X of tex2html_wrap_inline5075 of cardinality continuum. (That is, functions from Theorem 2.6.)

The classes tex2html_wrap_inline5829 and tex2html_wrap_inline5821 recently appeared in a 1993 paper of Darji [47], who constructed in ZFC a function tex2html_wrap_inline5843. Answering a question posed by Darji, this year Balcerzak, Ciesielski and Natkaniec proved the following theorem.


 theorem2237

The model satisfying Theorem 3.10(b) is, once again, the iterated perfect set model.

Another generalization of continuity is that of countable continuity: a function tex2html_wrap_inline5367 is is countably continuous if there exists a countable partition tex2html_wrap_inline5855 of tex2html_wrap_inline5075 such that the restriction of f to any tex2html_wrap_inline5861 is continuous. (See also Section 4.) In 1995 Darji gave the following combinatorial characterization of this notion.


 theorem2257

The characterization (tex2html_wrap_inline5873) cannot be proved in ZFC. This follows from a result of Cichon and Morayne [20] from 1988 which implies that in some models of ZFC (actually, when tex2html_wrap_inline5875 and tex2html_wrap_inline5877, where d is the dominating number) (tex2html_wrap_inline5873) is false. However, it is not known, whether the equivalence (tex2html_wrap_inline5873) can be proved in absence of CH, leading to the following open problem.


 problem2265

Another recent theorem concerning countable and symmetric continuities is the following theorem of Ciesielski and Szyszkowski, answering a question of L. Larson.


 theorem2269

We will finish this section with the following two interesting results. The first one has been proved independently in 1978 by Grande and Lipinski and in 1979 by Kharazishvili.


 theorem2274

This theorem has important consequences concerning the existence of solutions of the differential equation tex2html_wrap_inline5907 in the class of absolutely continuous functions. In 1992 Balcerzak [2] showed that in Theorem 3.13 the CH assumption can be weakened to tex2html_wrap_inline5165. However, the following problem remains open.


 problem2283

The second result is the following 1974 theorem of R. O. Davies.


 theorem2287


 problem2293

Note that Theorem 3.14 is related to Hilbert's Problem 13 (from his famous Paris lecture of 1900) and a 1957 theorem of Kolmogorov, in which he proves that every continuous function tex2html_wrap_inline5917 can be represented in a certain form (similar to the above) by continuous functions of one variable. An interesting account on this and related results can be found in a 1984 paper of Spreceher [133].


next up previous
Next: Cardinal functions in analysis Up: Set Theoretic Real Analysis Previous: New developments in classical